Republicanism and
Democracy
What
is republicanism? What
is its relationship with the theory and practice of
democracy?
As I
mentioned in the last essay, republicanism is regarded as one of the
four sources of democratic theory and practice. However, republicanism is
not attributable to ancient Greece; it was instead
exemplified by republican Rome (510-23 BC) and was
revived by the Italian city-states in the Middle Ages and
the Renaissance period.
Instead of emphasizing the importance of "rule by
the people" and the ideal of political equality (as the
classical democracy does), the classical republicanism advocates
self-government, mixed constitution and the need for a
government that reflects the interests not only of "the
many (the people)," but also of "the one (the monarch)"
and "the few (the aristocrats)," which in pre-modern days
were regarded as two distinct classes separate from the
people ("the many").
Republicanism was revived to fight against the claims of
natural rights to rule by monarchs and churches in
medieval Europe. As
such, the first key proposition of the Renaissance
republicanism is self-government. The classical
republicanism, facing various claims of natural rights to rule,
posits that a government should answer to no one other
than the community of people that it governs. The possibility and
institutions of self-government is at the core of the
classical republicanism, and the basic idea of
sovereignty of people is an important contribution of
republicanism to the modern theory of democracy. According to the
Renaissance republicanism, an independent and
self-governing people, together with the right of
citizens to participate in the government and a
constitutional framework assigning definite roles to
various social groups, forms the basis of liberty.
As a
corollary of the first proposition, the second important proposition
of the classical republicanism is that government power
should be derived from a great majority of the people,
not from god or other supernatural forces, nor from a
small group of privileged individuals. Since a
republican government has to be accountable to the
community as a whole, its power can only be derived from
the community as a whole.
In
addition, the classical republicanism posits that a government must
have a mixed constitution in order to be legitimate and
stable. Governments
that are in the exclusive control of "the one"
(monarchy), "the few" (aristocracy) or "the many"
(democracy) are illegitimate because none of the groups
can represent the community as a whole. Only a government that
incorporates the interests of all groups can be truly
legitimate. This
government is called a republican government. The republican government is
also stable because few people can complain that their
voices are not heard.
To
be sure, many of the classical republicanism's premises and
propositions are the same as those of democracy. The classical republicanism
and the classical democracy have the same goals: a
society sustained by civic virtue, in which people live a
happy life by devoting to public good and committing to
civic duties. People
are by nature political and social, according to the
classical political thinkers, and that is why people can
be happy only by living in a political association.
The
major difference between the classical republicanism and the
classical democracy lies in their different approaches to
the ideal society. Republicanism emphasizes the
importance of a mixed government stabilized by
incorporating the preferences of various classes of the
society (meaning, a great majority of the society), while
democracy focuses on the interests of "the many" which,
as mentioned above, was regarded in pre-modern ages as a
distinct and different class from "the one" (monarch) and
"the few" (aristocrats). In other words, the
classical republicanism demands a broad social basis for
self government (which, as we will see below, survives as
a central element of modern republicanism), and it posits
that any government controlled by one class is both
illegitimate and unstable; in contrast, the classical
democracy favors participation of the people ("the many")
in the political process and focuses on the ideals of liberty
and political equality.
There is another difference between the classical
republicanism and the classical democracy: while the
classical Greek democracy elates the potentials of civic
virtue, the Roman republicanism is more concerned with
the fragility of the civic virtue. As such, the classical
republicanism is closer to the modern liberalism's
assumptions about human nature; i.e., people are
short-sighted, impulsive and prone to vanity and passion. The major threat
to civic virtue, according to the classical republicanism, is
factions and political conflicts. As such, the major task of
republicanism is to design a system of mixed government
so that different interests are balanced and civic virtue
is maintained.
The
third difference between republicanism and democracy is historically
obvious. The
classical republicanism tries to find the truly legitimate
source of government power. In contrast, the classical
democracy does not concern itself with this question;
instead, the Athenians are more concerned with political
equality and political participation. To
Athenians, there is no question about legitimate source
of government power because the people is the government
and the government is the people.
In this sense, the classical republicanism
foreshadows the modern theory of representative
government and liberal democracy, because it implicitly
draws an distinction between "the government" and "the
people."
As
two examples, we will take a look at the Roman Empire and the city
republics in 12th-century Italy. The Roman Empire is regarded
as republican for two reasons. First, the Roman people were
regarded as highly virtuous and actively participating in
the political process. Second, with its system of
consuls, Senate, and tribunes of the people, the Roman
Empire maintained a mixed constitution that accommodated and
contained various social forces in the public
domain. Similarly, the
12th-century Italian city-states were republican because
of their ideals and institutions of self-government. Their systems of government
consisted of ruling councils headed by "podesta,"
officials with supreme executive and judicial
powers. Podesta were
elected officials with limited terms, and they were
accountable to the ruling councils and ultimately to the
citizens of the republic. In feudal Europe, the
self-governing Italian city republics were remarkable
because "they represented an explicit challenge to the
prevailing assumption that government must be regarded as a
God-given form of lordship" (Skinner).
The
classical republicanism later developed into two strands, which are
called protective republicanism and developmental
republicanism by Professor David Held. The major figure in
protective republicanism is Niccolo Machiavelli. An often misunderstood
thinker, Machiavelli points out the important connection
between republicanism and individual liberty. Unlike the classical
republicans, Machiavelli is among the first to foresee
the modern distinction between "the public" and "the
private." In
an often neglected but very important treatise titled The
Discourses, Machiavelli does not believe that there is a
natural or God-given way of organizing the political
order. To Machiavelli,
it is the task of "politics" to create order in the
world, and the objective of politics is to strive to
gain, maintain and use power.
At the same time, a nation can never become strong
and dominating unless its people have been enjoying
liberty, and the way to guarantee liberty is to have a mixed
constitution, not to meddle with people's private life,
and to expand by constantly engaging in wars. In the end, however,
Machiavelli places collective and national interest above
individual liberties, and he is concerned more with
national strength than with individual happiness. As such, like his
classical predecessors, Machiavelli is ultimately an
illiberal republican.
The
most important figure in developmental republicanism is J.J.
Rousseau. To Rousseau, the appeal of republicanism lies
not in its potential in guaranteeing the private liberty
of individuals, but in its ability to develop human
potentials and to unleash the "general will." Rousseau is no
liberal, but his influence in republican and democratic
theories is enduring. Like his classical
predecessors, Rousseau does not see the value of a
"private sphere;" indeed, Rousseau hates the private sphere. The existence of
a private sphere, with its accompanying inequality in wealth,
vanity and distortions, causes much of the human
sufferings. Rousseau
wants people to live independently and transparently, and
only the "general will" of the people can lead people to
happiness and freedom.
Rousseau sees a republican democracy as the way to
general will and freedom.
As
time passes by, the classical republicanism encounters various
difficulties.
One major difficulty is that it became harder and harder to
distinguish between "the one," "the few," and "the many"
in a society.
As such, modern republicanism has abandoned the
centrality of mixed constitution in classical
republicanism. Instead,
it emphasizes the importance of a broad social basis for
government power. As
James Madison puts it in his famous Federalist Papers No.
39, a republican government is "a government which
derives all its powers directly or indirectly from the
great body of the people, and is administered by persons
holding their offices during pleasure, for a limited
period, or during good behavior." In addition, as
Professor Robert Dahl points out, separation of power, not
mixed constitution, is more important to modern
republicanism.
In
modern terms, republicanism and democracy are no longer
incompatible. Instead, they tend to focus on different
aspects of the same political regime, and they are
complementary to each other.
Republicanism explains the source and nature of
governmental power in a democracy, while democracy
provides the mechanism for a government to be truly
republican. In
addition, the classical idea of mixed constitution, and
the modern idea of separation of power, can be regarded
as a way to control the problem of democratic tyranny.
Another difficulty for the classical republicanism is about
the size of a republic. Can a republic be a large
nation-state? How can
republican ideals be realized in a large
nation-state? Most of
the classical republicans are worried that, as a country
gets larger, a republican regime becomes unstable due to
the factional disputes and endless quarrels. However,
this worry was alleviated by the "discovery" of representative
government in the 18th and 19th century. We will discuss the theory
of representative government in the next essay. Additionally, the American
Federalists argued in 1787 that a republican regime is
not only possible, but also necessary, for a large
country like the United States of America.
How
to evaluate the classical republicanism? To be sure, most of the
liberal democratic states of our time have the remnants
of the classical mixed constitution. The United Kingdom, with its
system of the Queen (the monarch), the House of Lords
(with some remaining aristocratic arrangements) and the
House of Commons (representatives of the people), is a
quintessential example of mixed constitution in modern times. Even in the
United States, there are elements of democracy (the use of various
referenda), aristocracy (the existence of an entrenched
class of social and political elites), and monarchy (the
existence of a powerful President). The continuing
existence of mixed constitutions proves the enduring
influence of republicanism. More importantly, the
republican lesson that government power must be from a
great majority of the people has become a central element
of the modern theory and practice of democracy. When we examine
the modern liberal democratic states, we find that some of the core
propositions of the republican tradition --- such as its
anti-monarchical spirit and its concern with the
corruption of public life by private interests --- have
been maintained and combined with the later liberal ideas
and institutions.
(The
author is an associate at the New York law firm of Davis Polk &
Wardwell.
Opinions expressed here are solely those of the author's and
should not be attributed to Davis Polk & Wardwell.)
References:
1.
Dahl, Robert A. Democracy and Its Critiques. Yale University Press,
1989.
2.
Held, David. Models of Democracy (2nd Edition). Stanford University
Press, 1996.
3.
Machiavelli, Niccolo. The Discourses. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1983.
4.
Madison, James. The Federalist Papers, No. 39.
5.
Rousseau, J. J. The Social Contract. Harmondsworth: Penguin,
1968.